Renovating Marriage: The Requirements of
Mutual Respect
Justice
Minister Martin Cauchon has been passionate in
rejecting civil unions as an alternative to same-sex marriage, on the grounds
that separate is not equal and is a breach of human rights. The Prime Minister says he is persuaded by
that view. Advocates of same-sex
marriage argue such a union is “secondary…a separate room (from marriage)…nice
quarters (but) it isn’t the room everyone else gets” and that is discrimination. But is that correct?
Like
language, metaphors are not neutral.
They affect how we both perceive and analyze a situation, and give us
access to otherwise unavailable insights. The metaphor of marriage as a
building is apt. Institutions are
important metaphysical societal structures constructed through human
culture. In the case of marriage, the
‘establishing culture’ is found across all societies and spans millennia.
Same-sex marriage challenges that institutional building. Staying with the metaphor of a building, that
challenge can be viewed in two radically different ways
Advocates
of same-sex marriage see same-sex and opposite-sex unions as fundamentally the
same and those advocating separate institutions for marriage and civil unions
as barring the door to marriage with a specific goal of locking out same-sex
couples. That’s correctly viewed as
discrimination.
In
contrast, advocates of a two equal institutions approach see same-sex and
opposite-sex unions as fundamentally different.
Precisely because of that difference, separate institutions can be
equal. These people’s primary goal is
not to exclude same-sex couples from marriage.
It is, rather, to preserve important and unique functions of marriage,
especially at the societal level in relation to procreation and children and in
symbolizing genetic links between the generations. Same-sex marriage would necessarily change
those functions.
Consequently,
advocates of a two equal institutions approach, can see same-sex marriage
advocates as property developers who want either to tear down the historic
building of marriage or to keep just its façade and to eliminate what is, for
them, the primary substance and functions of marriage.
Tearing
down our heritage is never a neutral act and often results in irreplaceable
loss. We must, therefore, always be able
to justify change to a heritage - here marriage. Justification depends on the options
available and the reasons for our choice among them.
Three
options are open: To tear down (with or without keeping the façade) and build a
new and different institution. To refuse all renovations.
Or to make modifications that preserve the old,
because it is still needed, and accommodate the new - a ‘two different but
equal institutions’ approach.
Same-sex
marriage advocates support the first option. Some conservative people the
second. And many Canadians – probably the majority – the
third.
But
is the third approach, as same-sex marriage advocates claim, discriminatory in
its essence? If so, it is
unacceptable. To decide requires looking
at, first, the context in which separate but equal institutions are proposed,
second, whether there is a relevant difference between them, and, third, the
reasons for adopting that approach.
Rejection
of a ‘separate but equal’ approach on the grounds that it is necessarily
discrimination, is usually referenced to a 1954 judgment of the US Supreme
Court without any mention of the context in which that judgment was handed
down. The court concluded that” in the field of public education,
‘separate but equal’ has no place.
Separate educational facilities [on the basis of race] are inherently
unequal”. But that is not necessarily
true of establishing separate institutions in other areas on other grounds.
In
particular, it is not necessarily true of institutions for the public
recognition of committed adult relationships, when, as is true for marriage and
civil unions, they encompass different realities and carry different
symbolism. Indeed, it is not even true
of all separate educational institutions.
Separate schools for girls and boys - that is on the basis of sex not
race as in the Supreme Court case - can be equal and are not seen as
discriminatory by most people, although sex, like race, is normally a prohibited
ground of discrimination. That is
because reasons can determine whether a given act is discrimination.
Let’s
take another example, allocating shared hospital rooms. Allocating shared rooms on the basis of race
would be discrimination, but doing so on the basis of sex is not. Indeed, failure to do the latter can be a
breach of a person’s human rights and dignity.
The family of an old lady who died in a room shared with a young man is
still traumatized by their mother’s deep distress at finding herself in this
situation. In short, the same act can be
discrimination or not, depending on the reasons for undertaking it. Although normally we regard separating men
and women as discrimination, in the old lady’s case failure to do so was a
failure of respect.
Should
we equate homosexuality to race or to sex in the above examples in deciding on
a one or two institutions approach to same-sex unions? The central issue in that decision, as those
examples show, is: What is required in terms of respect? Some reasons for undertaking an act mean it
manifests respect, other reasons for the same act, that it shows disrespect.
To
reject same-sex marriage in the public square in order to affirm moral or other
objections to homosexuals is a failure of respect and would be
discrimination. To reject it because
marriage could no longer embody the inherently procreative relationship between
a man and a woman and, thereby, institutionalize and symbolize the functions of
marriage related to procreation and children is not discrimination. Many - one hopes the vast majority - of
opponents of same-sex marriage do not disrespect
homosexuals or their relationships. Yet
the same-sex marriage case is based almost entirely on equating being against
it with necessarily being against homosexuals, disrespecting them and thereby
breaching their human rights. That
connection needs to be challenged.
And
respect is not a one-sided issue. Same-sex marriage raises fundamental issues
of mutual respect, although this
seems not to be recognized by its advocates.
What is required to respect homosexual people and their committed
partnerships, and to respect people
for whom marriage institutionalizes and symbolizes the inherently procreative
relationship between a man and a woman?
The only “least invasive-of-both-streams-of-respect” response is to
legally recognize same-sex partnerships and keep marriage as the union of a man
and a woman. But, same-sex marriage
advocates reject that option outright.
Their
adamant stance can cause one to wonder.
Same-sex marriage will necessarily eliminate marriage as an institution
symbolizing heterosexuality, which is a goal of its advocates because they see
it as preferencing heterosexuality. At
the same time, they are very reassuring that admitting same-sex couples to
marriage cannot harm it and certainly not destroy it. But despite these reassurances, might the
fundamental change in the nature of marriage same-sex marriage would entail,
amount to a demolition rather than, as they claim, a renovation, especially
when the building is already fragile?
Sometimes, when undertaking renovations, developers find that all the
walls come tumbling down.